6
평가한
제품
280
계정에 있는
제품

chrimas 님이 최근에 작성한 평가

1-6/6개 항목을 표시 중
6명이 이 평가가 유용하다고 함
3명이 이 평가가 재미있다고 함
기록상 0.4시간 (평가 당시 0.3시간)
This game is incredible, but to understand it we must first take a journey into Hegelian dialectics.
“Hegel’s dialectics” refers to the particular dialectical method of argument employed by the 19th Century German philosopher, G.W.F. Hegel), which, like other “dialectical” methods, relies on a contradictory process between opposing sides. Whereas Plato’s “opposing sides” were people (Socrates and his interlocutors), however, what the “opposing sides” are in Hegel’s work depends on the subject matter he discusses. In his work on logic, for instance, the “opposing sides” are different definitions of logical concepts that are opposed to one another. In the Phenomenology of Spirit, which presents Hegel’s epistemology or philosophy of knowledge, the “opposing sides” are different definitions of consciousness and of the object that consciousness is aware of or claims to know. As in Plato’s dialogues, a contradictory process between “opposing sides” in Hegel’s dialectics leads to a linear evolution or development from less sophisticated definitions or views to more sophisticated ones later. The dialectical process thus constitutes Hegel’s method for arguing against the earlier, less sophisticated definitions or views and for the more sophisticated ones later. Hegel regarded this dialectical method or “speculative mode of cognition” (PR §10) as the hallmark of his philosophy and used the same method in the Phenomenology of Spirit [PhG], as well as in all of the mature works he published later—the entire Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences (including, as its first part, the “Lesser Logic” or the Encyclopaedia Logic [EL]), the Science of Logic [SL], and the Philosophy of Right [PR].

Note that, although Hegel acknowledged that his dialectical method was part of a philosophical tradition stretching back to Plato, he criticized Plato’s version of dialectics. He argued that Plato’s dialectics deals only with limited philosophical claims and is unable to get beyond skepticism or nothingness (SL-M 55–6; SL-dG 34–5; PR, Remark to §31). According to the logic of a traditional reductio ad absurdum argument, if the premises of an argument lead to a contradiction, we must conclude that the premises are false—which leaves us with no premises or with nothing. We must then wait around for new premises to spring up arbitrarily from somewhere else, and then see whether those new premises put us back into nothingness or emptiness once again, if they, too, lead to a contradiction. Because Hegel believed that reason necessarily generates contradictions, as we will see, he thought new premises will indeed produce further contradictions. As he puts the argument, then,

the scepticism that ends up with the bare abstraction of nothingness or emptiness cannot get any further from there, but must wait to see whether something new comes along and what it is, in order to throw it too into the same empty abyss. (PhG-M §79)

Hegel argues that, because Plato’s dialectics cannot get beyond arbitrariness and skepticism, it generates only approximate truths, and falls short of being a genuine science (SL-M 55–6; SL-dG 34–5; PR, Remark to §31; cf. EL Remark to §81). The following sections examine Hegel’s dialectics as well as these issues in more detail.
Hegel provides the most extensive, general account of his dialectical method in Part I of his Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences, which is often called the Encyclopaedia Logic [EL]. The form or presentation of logic, he says, has three sides or moments (EL §79). These sides are not parts of logic, but, rather, moments of “every concept”, as well as “of everything true in general” (EL Remark to §79; we will see why Hegel thought dialectics is in everything in section 3). The first moment—the moment of the understanding—is the moment of fixity, in which concepts or forms have a seemingly stable definition or determination (EL §80).

The second moment—the “dialectical” (EL §§79, 81) or “negatively rational” (EL §79) moment—is the moment of instability. In this moment, a one-sidedness or restrictedness (EL Remark to §81) in the determination from the moment of understanding comes to the fore, and the determination that was fixed in the first moment passes into its opposite (EL §81). Hegel describes this process as a process of “self-sublation” (EL §81). The English verb “to sublate” translates Hegel’s technical use of the German verb aufheben, which is a crucial concept in his dialectical method. Hegel says that aufheben has a doubled meaning: it means both to cancel (or negate) and to preserve at the same time (PhG §113; SL-M 107; SL-dG 81–2; cf. EL the Addition to §95). The moment of understanding sublates itself because its own character or nature—its one-sidedness or restrictedness—destabilizes its definition and leads it to pass into its opposite. The dialectical moment thus involves a process of self-sublation, or a process in which the determination from the moment of understanding sublates itself, or both cancels and preserves itself, as it pushes on to or passes into its opposite.

Now that we've covered this, I can move on to the bulk of the review.
Oh boy cheese!
10/10
2022년 1월 7일에 게시되었습니다.
이 평가가 유용한가요? 아니요 재미있음 어워드
1명이 이 평가가 유용하다고 함
기록상 2.7시간 (평가 당시 2.7시간)
more catboys
2022년 1월 2일에 게시되었습니다.
이 평가가 유용한가요? 아니요 재미있음 어워드
728명이 이 평가가 유용하다고 함
251명이 이 평가가 재미있다고 함
5
9
20
2
2
2
5
4
3
2
2
26
기록상 203.2시간 (평가 당시 140.1시간)
monky
2020년 12월 3일에 게시되었습니다.
이 평가가 유용한가요? 아니요 재미있음 어워드
아직 아무도 이 평가가 유용하다고 하지 않음
기록상 0.3시간 (평가 당시 0.3시간)
fantastic game, would recommend to anyone interested in CBT
2020년 10월 20일에 게시되었습니다.
이 평가가 유용한가요? 아니요 재미있음 어워드
아직 아무도 이 평가가 유용하다고 하지 않음
기록상 118.6시간 (평가 당시 80.2시간)
best game i ever play
2020년 9월 20일에 게시되었습니다.
이 평가가 유용한가요? 아니요 재미있음 어워드
4명이 이 평가가 유용하다고 함
기록상 809.5시간 (평가 당시 309.7시간)
I love this game its just right for me style
2017년 12월 14일에 게시되었습니다.
이 평가가 유용한가요? 아니요 재미있음 어워드
1-6/6개 항목을 표시 중